Trending
Opinion: How will Project 2025 impact game developers?
The Heritage Foundation's manifesto for the possible next administration could do great harm to many, including large portions of the game development community.
Featured Blog | This community-written post highlights the best of what the game industry has to offer. Read more like it on the Game Developer Blogs or learn how to Submit Your Own Blog Post
On diegesis, Left 4 Dead, Donald Rumsfeld, and Squash
Note to those that have been following this series:
I’ve taken quite some time with this final entry. The truth is that pretty much all of it had already been written some time ago. But in the writing of it, I came to the conclusion that the shoehorning in as examples of some games I had made was exactly that—it was distracting from the central topic I had set out to examine. And once I began to question my motives, it became increasingly difficult to get myself to even post the dang thing.
I’ve rather failed thus far to establish what a mechanical narrative even is, why it should matter that we have such a specific and contained concept in our toolbox of ideas—the whole point of this series. And trying to define it by using such obscure examples just wasn’t working. The examples themselves needed too much explaining, significantly muddling the idea of the mechanical narrative.
To be fair to myself, some of the topics I wanted to address by bringing up those examples were and are genuinely useful here—particularly the observation that the win conditions of a game, and whether they even exist or matter to the player, greatly impacts the player’s mechanical experience and mechanical narrative. (Without trying to sound too ridiculous, the question, “What is winning?” is in fact quite practical and informative when considering mechanical narratives.) At any rate, though I may at some point return and talk about those games, I’ve decided to conclude the series with the following post, without further mention of them (as originally promised).
My apologies if I have kept anyone waiting.
The Difference between Mechanical and Procedural Narratives
Commenter D F mentioned on the last post that the types of narratives we are talking about should not be composed of narrative “events”, that they should be systemic and generated through process. I am actually in agreement with this (or rather, would say that they simply are, as opposed to should be), and am particularly thankful for the comment bringing up the term “procedural narrative”.
The distinct entity I have been trying to describe in this series (the mechanical narrative) is in fact different from procedural narratives. Traditionally, when we say procedural narrative, we are referring to narratives that have randomized elements, where the elements themselves (and usually the general plot parts of the story) have already been prefabricated. The “procedure” part is the algorithm used to link these elements together.
As such, procedural narratives are still about diegetic actors (e.g. non-player characters, the avatar/player character, etc.) and plot elements, whereas in mechanical narratives, the actors are the actual player(s) and the game itself. In a procedural narrative, the algorithm or “rules” are used to generate a story. In a mechanical narrative, the rules themselves essentially are the story.
Let’s back up a bit. What the heck is a “diegetic actor”? Briefly, the difference between a diegetic and non-diegetic actor is more or less the same as the difference between the player character and the player. We can dig into this a bit further with Wikipedia’s article on diegesis in film:
The classical distinction between the diegetic mode and the mimetic mode relate to the difference between the epos (or epic poetry) and drama. The "epos" relates stories by telling them through narration, while drama enacts stories through direct embodiment (showing) [my emphases].
In terms of classical poetics, the cinema is an epic form that utilizes dramatic elements; this is determined by the technologies of the camera and editing. Even in a spatially and temporally continuous scene (mimicking the theatrical situation, as it were), the camera chooses where to look for us. In a similar way, editing causes us to jump from one place (and/or time) to another, whether it be somewhere else in the room, or across town. This jump is a form of narration; it is as if a narrator whispers to us: "meanwhile, on the other side of the forest".
It is for this reason that the "story-world" in cinema is referred to as "diegetic"; elements that belong to the film's narrative world are diegetic elements. This is why, in the cinema, we may refer to the film's diegetic world.
To make a poor analogy via film, we can say that traditional and procedural narratives in games are like the stories contained within the content of movies—they exist as the game’s diegetic world. In this analogy, mechanical narratives, then, would describe the processes the viewer of a movie experiences while interpreting the film’s narration—the story told by examining how the various camera and editing techniques alter the viewer’s understanding of the narration.
Again, this is a rather terrible analogy, but the point is that a mechanical narrative’s story is not within the content, but within the dialectic between the player and the device.
Designing a mechanical narrative, then, is about crafting experiential possibilities that become understood as a “story”, as opposed to crafting a story that is then experienced. The confusion arises in that the experience of experiencing a dynamic or interactive story itself can produce a mechanical narrative. The story structure in games, after all, is also a set of rules to be followed.
Even more confusingly, rules can be both diegetic and non-diegetic at the same time. This, of course, is because the player character is the diegetic version of the player. And there are rules that both the player and the player character abide by, if ultimately for different reasons. (This is what I was partially referring to when I wrote in Part 2 that verbs have both narrative and mechanical definitions.)
Diegesis in Left 4 Dead
For instance, does Left 4 Dead produce procedural narratives or mechanical ones? Well, the answer is both, and simultaneously. But the difference between the experience of the player and the experience of the player character should be clear.
A low-health player character is not making a mechanical decision when it self-sacrificingly gives some pills to a fellow survivor, while the player could very well be making a purely mechanical decision based on his assessment of their respective skills or foreknowledge of upcoming health caches. Conversely, the player could be forgoing all mechanical considerations and likelihoods in order to play along with the procedural story—to assimilate with the player character’s motivations. A Versus game of L4D skews mechanical because the goal is no longer survival of the player characters, but point taking; the reality of the gameworld takes a far backseat.
To develop the example further, a player that decides to leave the extraction point in the finale to help out a downed player in the face of an oncoming tank and horde is either making a diegetic decision to “leave no man behind” or an extra-diegetic one to see if the player can succeed the challenge against the odds (or both). A player that extracts by himself when all other team members have been incapacitated is making an extra-diegetic decision based on the rule that the campaign will successfully finish if just one person gets on board (to avoid repeating the finale, and potentially failing entirely), or a non-diegetic decision that self-interested “winning” is more important than teamplay.
The labeling of these motivations is actually subject to change depending on the player. The decision to “leave no man behind” can also be non-diegetic—it can be an external principle and self-imposed rule the player follows anyway, in any situation, without any prompting from the game or its environment and reality. Similarly, one suspects that the diegetic characters of L4D would rather see that a fellow survivor escapes than remains behind to die for a hopeless cause, so the lone survivor scenario could conceivably be an act of extreme diegetic roleplay.
At any rate, a mechanical narrative, isn’t really about retelling of the player’s mechanical decisions per se. It is more about the player managing the tensions between the game’s diegetic reality and the player’s non- and/or extra- diegetic goals—of how the play was determined, and not so much the play itself. I would even go so far as to argue that mechanical narratives are only possible when the distinction between these motivated systems can be felt, through either involuntary difference or deliberate, conscious, voluntary assimilation.
Donald Rumsfeld and Squash
As an extreme (perhaps slightly too political, and rather insensitive) example of how the interaction between various levels of diegesis in gameplay can shape a narrative, let’s consider former Defense Secretary Donald Rumsfeld and the game of squash.
Mr. Rumsfeld has testified that “his ideas about transforming the military into a smaller, more agile force, like the one he pushed for in invading Iraq, were influenced by his squash playing.” The above linked article describes Mr. Rumsfeld’s play as follows:
Rather than tricky bank shots off the walls, a move that better-skilled players favor, Mr. Rumsfeld plays with power, hitting the ball hard and ending points quickly. And he relentlessly attacks his opponent’s confidence.
Mr. Rumsfeld himself noted, “When I pass [the opponent] in a shot and it’s a well-played hard shot, I saw speed kills. And it does. If you can do something very fast you can get your job done and save a lot of lives”. This was his mechanical narrative.
Unfortunately for this case, what we can see in this narrative is a need to create conditions that make power shots more favorable than bank shots. Which is to say, instead of bending his non-diegetic goals, Mr. Rumsfeld insisted that extra-diegetic structures be modified or imposed to suit his non-diegetic needs. A few examples (again, from the article):
- Mr. Zimmerman has never actually played his boss. But he says he has noticed that Mr. Rumsfeld, 74, often wins points because, after hitting a shot, he does not get out of the way so his opponent has a chance to return the ball, a practice known in squash as “clearing.”
- [Despite this, and given that interference/obstructions are inevitable in squash] Mr. Di Rita [a former regular partner] concedes that Mr. Rumsfeld rarely offers or asks for “lets,” a replay point when one player feels aggrieved.
- In squash, Mr. Rumsfeld’s main advantage over more capable and fitter players is that he refuses to play anything but “hardball,” a variation of the game that was once common in the United States but has largely died out over the last decade. Most competitors now play the international game, which uses a softer ball and a wider court, requiring more running and allowing more creative shot-making. The harder ball favored by Mr. Rumsfeld tends to come back to the center of the court, so players do not have to move as much to return it.
This history, then, led to a series of decisions which reflected the expectation that “diegetic” reality would meet a set of “extra-diegetic” rules and impositions that, in this case, ultimately only held true for the person dictating them, for the specific conditions under which they were conceived.
The United States had a “short-war strategy,” [retired Army general] Keane complained to Rumsfeld in September 2006. “Nowhere in it is there a plan to defeat the insurgency ourselves.” Changing course, he explained, would require as many as 28,000 more troops. Keane describes Rumsfeld as shocked at the news, “as if he was hearing it for the first time.” American forces, it turned out, were a bit too flexible [my emphasis]. They were configured in such a way that they could pack up and leave anytime, and that was not lost on the insurgents, or on bystanders picking sides.
As we now know, it was the “surge”, the vast increase of troops on the ground in Iraq, which eventually brought that war to a close. (This is a tremendously simplified narrative. It’s also debatable as to how much direct influence the Secretary of Defense even has over troop size and structure.)
From this example, we can see that it is the contingencies created by the entanglements of all three diegetic, non-, and extra-, which produce mechanical narratives. The diegetic actualities of the sport of squash (the need to move around the court, etc.) clash with Mr. Rumsfeld’s non-diegetic realities of being 74 years old but desirous of beating much younger, and in some cases better, opponents, which leads to extra-diegetic choices of hardballing and non-clearing. This produces the mechanical narrative that “speed kills”. The narrative is true because of the way the rules have been played.
Later on, the “non-diegetic” goals of speed and flexibility (also partially motivated by “diegetic” domestic political realities, though one must remember the strong support for the war by the American public at the time) lead to “extra-diegetic” dictations on troop structures and strategies which in the end fail take into consideration certain necessities of the “diegetic” real world. This produces the mechanical narrative that a military invasion that seeks to establish complete politico-cultural regime change can’t be “won” through “flexibility” and “speed”—the tragic narrative that the apparently truthful lessons of squash just did not apply in this case. This narrative is true because of the way the rules must be played.
In this extended analogy, the former narrative would be a “player-driven” one, whereas the latter would be “designer-driven”.
I do not mean, here, to trivialize war as an impersonal “game”; the last thing I would want to do is to make light of the death of so many, and I sincerely apologize if this analysis has caused any offense or hurt. What I am saying, however, is that the degree to which mechanical narratives can shape our expectations and thinking can be devastatingly [or gloriously] real.
The very thing that can make them feel so victorious can cause them to be blinding, particularly negatively so when we fail to realize that the “game”—any object upon which we are projecting our mechanical narratives—has changed, or was never what we thought it to be.
Designer Driven Mechanical Narratives
I had originally intended to title this series with the above header. The idea was to focus on the fact that mechanical narratives can be designer defined, and that this has nothing whatsoever to do with dictated “narration”. It is the degree to which diegetic or extra-diegetic rules shape, impose themselves upon, or eclipse the player’s non- or extra- diegetic goals that determines the amount of designer intent entering into the player’s experience. But, as I hope the above examples have made clear, these distinctions are actually quite fluid, and both involuntary and voluntary assimilation can generate strong narratives.
At any rate, the point once again is that we don’t have to leave the strength of these narratives up to chance, and being deliberate doesn’t necessarily mean “non-dynamic” or “non-linear”. We can be methodical in their construction simply by careful, considered crafting of the rules. By studying the implicit demands of the mechanics, and the range of possible motivations the player might approach the game with—and by expressly designing for, or designing in, the tensions between them—we can do much to insure that an engaging narrative arises, or to even specifically shape them.
The final thing I want to say about this topic is why the concept of a mechanical narrative even matters. Game apologists will often bring up the idea of the uniqueness of games. This almost always goes to the mainstay that games offer “interaction” and “choice.” But these things in themselves are rather meaningless—even DVD menus offer as much.
The true uniqueness of games as a medium is that a genuine dialog arises every time a game is played. A clash, or at least some sort of integration, between the rules of the game and the rules of the player happens every time, and that is what gives ludic interaction meaning. Interaction, therefore, is just a word—and an inadequate, non-specific one—describing the consumption of games, much as reading a book, or watching a movie describes the consumption of those forms of media.
The utility of the concept of “mechanical narrative”, then—or whatever we decide to call it—is to give name to that clash, that dialog. And it matters in that, through specificity and recognition, it helps us think and talk more directly about what the rules and design of a game do to the players that play it.
Read more about:
Featured BlogsYou May Also Like